On Thu, 20 Nov 2008, Alex Smith wrote: > Imagine R1 saying "Goethe CAN deregister by paying > 1 Stem" and R2 saying "Goethe CANNOT deregister";
Both of these are claims on what can and can't be done by an action, and neither defines the state of (de)registration. It's a bad example. A better example is: R1 says "Voting Index Is a number." R2 says "Goethe CAN set the Voting index to Green Cheese." I'm claiming that this basic definition "is a number" is an (albeit implicit) claim of precedence. Why can I claim that? Well... > When there's an obvious direct conflict > between two rules, as there is here, there isn't an implicit claim of > precedence on either; there's an explicit clash, and the more powerful > rule, or the rule with the lower number, takes precedence. An important missing piece in your argument is that I used R1586 to argue for definitional preference. R2 is actually in conflict with R1586 as well as R1. In particular from R1586: "then that entity and its properties continue to exist to whatever extent is possible under the new definitions." ^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^ It is not possible for the Voting Index to be Green Cheese under its definition as a number. As R2 would allow me to set it against the R1 "new definitions", R2 is in conflict with R1586 (and in the current case, by numerical precedence, R1586 wins). Finally, we're *both* making implicit claims. You're claiming the fact that someone CAN set a numerical index to Green Cheese is an implicit definition that the numerical index has a defined green cheese state. I'm saying that the definition implicitly claims precedence (which only works at the same Power to override numerical precedence) and forbids a green cheese state under R1586 as it is not possible under the new definitions. I still find my implicit claim far less of a stretch than yours. -Goethe