On Thu, 20 Nov 2008, Alex Smith wrote:
> Imagine R1 saying "Goethe CAN deregister by paying
> 1 Stem" and R2 saying "Goethe CANNOT deregister"; 

Both of these are claims on what can and can't be done by an action,
and neither defines the state of (de)registration. It's a bad example.  
A better example is:  R1 says "Voting Index Is a number."  R2 says 
"Goethe CAN set the Voting index to Green Cheese."  I'm claiming
that this basic definition "is a number" is an (albeit implicit) claim 
of precedence.  Why can I claim that?  Well...

> When there's an obvious direct conflict
> between two rules, as there is here, there isn't an implicit claim of
> precedence on either; there's an explicit clash, and the more powerful
> rule, or the rule with the lower number, takes precedence.

An important missing piece in your argument is that I used R1586 to
argue for definitional preference. R2 is actually in conflict with R1586
as well as R1.  In particular from R1586:
                                                         "then that
      entity and its properties continue to exist to whatever extent
      is possible under the new definitions."
         ^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^
It is not possible for the Voting Index to be Green Cheese under its
definition as a number.  As R2 would allow me to set it against the R1 
"new definitions", R2 is in conflict with R1586 (and in the current case, 
by numerical precedence, R1586 wins).

Finally, we're *both* making implicit claims.  You're claiming the fact 
that someone CAN set a numerical index to Green Cheese is an implicit 
definition that the numerical index has a defined green cheese state.  
I'm saying that the definition implicitly claims precedence (which only 
works at the same Power to override numerical precedence) and forbids
a green cheese state under R1586 as it is not possible under the new 
definitions.  I still find my implicit claim far less of a stretch than 
yours.

-Goethe


Reply via email to