On Monday, January 13, 2025 at 11:58:38 PM UTC+1 Jesse Mazer wrote:


Doesn't Godel's theorem only apply to systems whose output can be mapped to 
judgments about the truth-value of propositions in first-order arithmetic? 
A cellular automaton would seem to have "evolving quantities and/or 
qualities through numerical or some other equivalent formalism's means", 
but Godel's theorem places no limitations on our ability to compute the 
behavior of the cellular automaton for N time-increments, for any finite 
value of N, so I would think Godel's theorem would likewise place no 
limitations on our ability to compute the physical evolution of the 
universe's state for any finite time interval. For some cellular automata 
it may be possible to set up the initial state so that the question of 
whether some theorem is ever proved true or false by the Peano axioms (or 
other axioms for arithmetic) is equivalent to a question about whether the 
automaton ever arrives at a certain configuration of cells, so Godel's 
theorem may imply limits on our ability to answer such questions, but this 
is a question about whether something happens in an infinite time period. I 
assume there are similar limitations on our ability to determine whether 
certain physical states will ever occur in an infinite future 
(straightforwardly if we build a physical machine that derives theorems 
from the Peano axioms, or a machine that derives conclusions about whether 
various Turing programs halt), but most of what physicists do is concerned 
with predictions over finite time intervals, I don't see how Godel's 
theorem would pose any fundamental obstacles to doing that.

Jesse


Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem states that any sufficiently strong 
formal system (capable of arithmetic) contains statements that are 
undecidable—neither provable nor disprovable within that system. The second 
theorem says such a system cannot prove its own consistency from its own 
axioms. These are statements about provability in formal theories. They are 
not directly about whether you can compute a finite number of steps in a 
system like a cellular automaton.

You can absolutely compute, step by step, the evolving states of a (finite) 
cellular automaton for N time steps, and Gödel’s theorems do not say you 
can’t. They say something deeper: if your formal axioms are strong enough 
to represent integer arithmetic (like Peano Arithmetic or any 
Turing-complete formulation), there will be statements expressible within 
that framework which it cannot resolve. That’s a statement about what can 
or cannot be proven within the system, not about whether a machine can run 
a simulation for some finite time. 

You also assume that Gödel’s incompleteness only restricts what can happen 
in an “infinite time” scenario. For example: “Well, sure, there might be 
some question about whether a certain configuration arises eventually, but 
for finite intervals we have no Gödel-limited obstacles.” This misreads 
Gödel: Gödel’s first theorem does not hinge on infinite time steps; it is 
about the intrinsic logical structure of the formal system. Even for 
trivial seeming statements involving finite objects (e.g., “this specific 
integer has property P”), the theorem shows there can be statements that 
the system cannot prove or disprove. It’s not that you can’t “run the 
simulation long enough,” but rather that the theory itself cannot settle 
certain propositions at all.

Yes, questions about infinite evolution (like “does the automaton ever 
reach configuration C at some unbounded time?”) can become unanswerable in 
principle if they encode the halting problem or an arithmetic statement. 
But Gödel’s point is more general: the existence of some undecidable 
statements is guaranteed, quite apart from whether they manifest in an 
infinite-time scenario or not.

If a cellular automaton is known to be Turing-complete (i.e., it can 
replicate the behavior of a universal Turing machine), then in principle it 
inherits exactly the logical limitations that come from being universal. 
That means there will be statements about the automaton’s global behavior 
(for instance, whether it will ever reach a certain state from a certain 
initial condition) that are undecidable. This “undecidability” is not about 
lacking the ability to compute it up to step N—rather, it’s about no 
possible proof or disproof existing within a certain formal system’s axioms 
regarding some carefully constructed properties of that automaton.

Put another way, if the theory describing the automaton and its states is 
as powerful as something like Peano Arithmetic, then Gödel’s result shows 
there exist statements about that automaton’s behavior that the theory 
can’t settle.

This doesn’t contradict our practical ability to simulate the automaton for 
finite steps. It simply highlights that some high-level questions (like a 
halting-like problem for the automaton) could be undecidable in the strong 
sense Gödel identified.

A final misconception is that the existence of straightforward computable 
truths (e.g., “2 + 2 = 4” or “state s follows from state s_0 after N 
steps”) somehow negates Gödel’s theorems. It does not. Gödel never claimed 
“no statement is decidable,” but rather that “there exist some statements 
that are undecidable.” The presence of plenty of decidable truths or 
effectively computable processes is not an escape hatch from 
incompleteness. A formal system can easily prove 2 + 2 = 4, yet still fail 
to prove or disprove a Gödel-type sentence.

Therefore, you seem to mix up “we can compute local steps easily” with 
“therefore there’s no deeper limit on provability.” A huge jump. 
Incompleteness is about the existence of certain statements the theory 
cannot decide at all—not about whether we can check how a system evolves 
over N steps.

It can help to see Gödel’s message as a reminder that once you allow 
arithmetic (or an equivalent notion of proof) into your theoretical 
framework, you automatically inherit logical “gaps” you cannot fill from 
within that framework. Consequently, every time a new observation or 
phenomenon appears to contradicts some current theory of the universe in 
the news feeds—be it quantum mechanical or cosmological—standard practice 
is to say, “We’ll just extend or refine the system,” hoping that, in 
principle, you can patch all holes. From a Gödelian perspective, however, 
such hopes are naive, even if made by top researchers constantly; you 
cannot achieve a neat, airtight completeness once you’re in the realm of 
arithmetic-level expressiveness. Each new theory you devise may bear 
fruit—often very real, practical fruit—and it may rectify certain 
anomalies, but it cannot be the final word, because no single formal system 
can be both consistent and complete about everything you can say in it.

That’s why it’s no surprise to someone with a minimum of familiarity in 
Gödel’s work that the mind spawns endless re-interpretations and 
frameworks—especially in quantum mechanics—that run counter to some 
“standard” stance. They’re not necessarily wrong or right in a final sense; 
rather, they’re new attempts at formalizing a larger or more nuanced slice 
of reality. As Gödel implies, there is an unbounded supply of possible 
formal systems you can keep proposing, and many do yield fresh insights or 
engineering progress. But none will eliminate the fundamental 
incompleteness that arises once you assume enough structure to reason 
arithmetically. So the cycle of “discover contradiction → revise theory → 
see new contradictions” is essentially built into the logical fabric of how 
we formalize our knowledge—Gödel merely gave us a precise way to see why 
that cycle never fully ends.

This is also why a ToE, when reliant on evolving quantities/qualities and 
including physics, has to be “informal” with Gödel in mind. And that’s what 
this list got so wrong with so many years of splitting hairs with Bruno: 
informal reasoning can be rigorous. And regarding ToE post Gödel, it has to 
be that way! All the attacks on Bruno of the “You can’t be serious!” or 
“that is not a rigorous argument/proof”, or “how can informal thought 
experiments be taken seriously” - sort just miss the point/lack familiarity 
with Gödel. 

I hope this provides some clarity. I’ll have to ask forgiveness for not 
being able to participate in discussions and reply as much as I’d like but 
I have too many time restraints atm and not enough time to even read. 
Hence, my call for either some moderation, more restraint, or whatever is 
needed to have a more organized list focused more on the ToE topic, instead 
of spoon feeding, bad faith arguments, or troll engagement/permissiveness. 
Yes, of course we can talk Trump politics, but not in some trivial "caveman 
truth" asserting way. I hope you understand. In closing, I suggest looking 
at the work (Gödel) and making up your own mind to decide for yourself 
whether Gödel’s theorems apply or not, so you don’t have to take my word 
for it, as you shouldn't.

-- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email 
to everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit 
https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/3e559b07-1b9d-4682-9642-c1eaf1d358f4n%40googlegroups.com.

Reply via email to