I definitely did not read the whole thing... but it seemed pretty
coherent... and I am glad you are having fun with the plagiarism bots.

Best,
Eric

-----------
Eric P. Charles, Ph.D.
Head, Data Analytics and Delivery
Human Capital Data Modernization and Management (HCDMM)
Office of Personnel Management (OPM)
American University - Adjunct Instructor
<echar...@american.edu>


On Wed, Jan 22, 2025 at 11:42 PM Nicholas Thompson <thompnicks...@gmail.com>
wrote:

> It's odd to me so may people respond to AI as a way for somebody [else] to
> get away with something, rather than as a way for "me" to do somehthing
> creative and interesting.   George has taught me so much in the last three
> months about atmospheric dynamics, but only because I treat him with the
> same skepticism that I treat all of you.  I makes want to go back to
> college teaching so I can be part of the generation that teaches young
> people to use AI to speed their own creativity and independence of
> thought.   "My professor told me to day that entropy has to do with the
> distribution of objects in space"   What do you think of that, George?   I
> can say without any meanness of spirit what so ever that the conversation
> we have below, George and I, is at least as satisfying INTELLECTUALLY as
> any I have had with any of you.  Why should we deny it to our students, or
> to one another, for that matter.
>
> You said:
> "My professor told me to day that entropy has to do with the distribution
> of objects in physical space. What do you think of that, George?"
> ChatGPT said:
>
> Entropy is closely related to distributions, but it's more nuanced than
> just the distribution of objects in physical space. Here's what I'd say:
>
> Entropy fundamentally quantifies the number of ways a system can be
> arranged while maintaining the same macroscopic properties, like energy or
> volume. In statistical mechanics, it's tied to the probability distribution
> of microstates—the microscopic configurations of a system.
>
> While objects in physical space might be part of the story (e.g., the
> positions of particles in a gas), entropy is broader. It encompasses energy
> distributions, momentum states, and other degrees of freedom, not just
> spatial arrangement. In thermodynamics, entropy measures the amount of
> "disorder" or the system's progression toward equilibrium.
>
> So, your professor's statement captures part of the concept, but it's
> simplified. Entropy involves distributions across *all* relevant
> variables in a system—not just the spatial ones. Does that align with what
> you're exploring?
> You said:
> well, George I am beginning to think that distribution in physical space
> is a consequence of the the equilibration of microstates, not an example of
> it. In fact, I am beginning to think that the random placement particles
> within space is handy visual metaphor for entropy but not the thing itself.
> What do you say to that, George?
> ChatGPT said:
>
> I think you're onto something insightful, Nick. The distribution of
> particles in physical space often serves as an illustrative metaphor, but
> you're right—it’s not the essence of entropy itself.
>
> Entropy, at its core, relates to the *equilibration of microstates*—the
> tendency of a system to maximize the number of accessible microstates
> consistent with its constraints. This equilibration doesn't privilege any
> specific type of variable, spatial or otherwise. Physical space is just one
> of many dimensions (e.g., energy, momentum, spin) over which microstates
> can be distributed.
>
> The visual metaphor of particles "randomly distributed in space" is useful
> because it's tangible. It’s easier to grasp than abstract concepts like
> phase space or energy distributions. However, as you suggest, that
> randomness is a *result* of the system seeking equilibrium by exploring
> all accessible microstates—not the defining feature of entropy.
>
> In essence, entropy is the measure of *possibilities*, not just spatial
> randomness. The spatial metaphor is like a shadow—it gives you an
> impression of the thing, but it’s not the thing itself.
> You said:
> There is a contradiction in your reply above, George. Could you please
> address it. Is "position" a microstate like velocity and momentum in the x,
> y, and z directions? Or is everything essential about position already
> captured by these six microstates?
> ChatGPT said:
>
> You're absolutely right to call out the potential contradiction, Nick. Let
> me clarify and address the heart of the issue regarding position and its
> role in the description of a system's microstates.
> 1. *Is Position a Microstate?*
>
> Yes, position can be considered part of a microstate description. In
> classical mechanics, a microstate is typically defined by specifying both
> the positions (x,y,z) and the momenta (px,py,pz) of all particles in the
> system. Together, these six variables per particle fully describe the state
> of the system in phase space. Position isn't redundant; it's an independent
> variable alongside momentum.
> 2. *Does Momentum Fully Capture Position?*
>
> No, momentum does not fully capture position. While momentum tells us how
> a particle is moving, it doesn't specify where the particle is located. For
> instance, two particles could have the same momentum but be in entirely
> different positions, leading to distinct microstates.
> 3. *Why the Confusion?*
>
> The confusion might arise because, in some contexts (e.g., quantum
> mechanics), position and momentum are intertwined through the uncertainty
> principle. However, in classical mechanics and statistical mechanics, they
> are treated as independent variables that together define the system's
> state.
> 4. *Reconciling the Contradiction*
>
> In my earlier reply, I unintentionally conflated position with a derived
> "visual metaphor" of spatial randomness, which might have implied that
> position is less essential. However, in the rigorous description of
> entropy, position is just as fundamental as momentum. The "random
> placement" metaphor can be useful for intuition, but the deeper truth is
> that position contributes directly to the system's phase space and
> therefore to its entropy.
>
> Would this clarification align with your understanding?
> You said:
> George: Please say more concerning what you mean by : The "random
> placement" metaphor can be useful for intuition, but the deeper truth is
> that position contributes directly to the system's phase space and
> therefore to its entropy.
> ChatGPT said:
>
> Absolutely, Nick—let’s unpack that further.
> *The "Random Placement" Metaphor*
>
> The idea of "random placement" often shows up in simplified explanations
> of entropy, especially in introductory contexts. For example:
>
>    - A gas in a box is said to "spread out" to fill the container, which
>    is often visualized as particles randomly scattering in space.
>    - The "random placement" metaphor creates the impression that entropy
>    is merely about achieving spatial uniformity, as though the particles'
>    positions alone determine the disorder or entropy.
>
> This metaphor is helpful because it gives a tangible, visual way to think
> about entropy increasing as systems move toward equilibrium. However, it's
> an incomplete picture.
> ------------------------------
> *Position's Role in Phase Space*
>
> The deeper truth lies in how position contributes to the *phase space* of
> the system. In classical mechanics:
>
>    - A particle's microstate is defined by its position (x,y,z) and
>    momentum (px,py,pz).
>    - The *phase space* is the multidimensional space of all possible
>    combinations of these variables for all particles in the system.
>
> Entropy arises from counting the number of accessible microstates in this
> phase space, which includes both position and momentum coordinates.
> Position is therefore not a mere afterthought but a fundamental aspect of
> the system's configuration.
> ------------------------------
> *Why Phase Space Matters More Than Position Alone*
>
> Entropy is about maximizing the *volume* of accessible phase space under
> the system’s constraints. This means:
>
>    - If you only considered positions, you'd ignore a significant portion
>    of the system's microstate diversity—specifically, the momentum degrees of
>    freedom.
>    - Spatial distributions (like particles spreading uniformly) are often
>    consequences of maximizing phase space volume, not direct causes of high
>    entropy. For instance, a gas uniformly filling a container corresponds to
>    many microstates in phase space, but the "uniform filling" is a result of
>    the system sampling all configurations.
>
> ------------------------------
> *Entropy Beyond the Visual Metaphor*
>
> The metaphor of random spatial placement simplifies entropy to the visible
> world of positions, but entropy fundamentally counts possibilities:
>
>    1. *Position Space*: Particles can occupy different regions of space.
>    2. *Momentum Space*: Particles can have various momenta, which
>    significantly increases the number of microstates.
>    3. The combination of these spaces—phase space—is what entropy
>    measures.
>
> So, while random placement is a *consequence* of entropy maximization (in
> cases like gases filling a box), the deeper truth is that entropy reflects
> the system's tendency to maximize all available microstates in phase space.
> This richer understanding goes beyond the spatial visualization.
>
> Does this deepen the distinction you’re seeking?
> You said:
> I understood x, y, and z to be velocity vectors, not positions. Was I
> wrong?
> ChatGPT said:
>
> Great question, Nick! Let’s clarify the distinction between *position
> vectors* and *velocity vectors* and how they relate to entropy and phase
> space.
> *Position vs. Velocity Vectors*
>
>    1.
>
>    *Position Vectors (x,y,z)*
>    These specify the spatial location of a particle in three-dimensional
>    physical space. For example:
>    - If a particle is in a box, x,y,z tell you where the particle is
>       inside that box.
>    2.
>
>    *Velocity Vectors (vx,vy,vz)*
>    These specify how fast the particle is moving and in which direction.
>    They are related to momentum (px,py,pz) via the relationship:
>    p
>
> =mv
>
>    2.
>
>    where m is the particle’s mass.
>
> ------------------------------
> *Phase Space and Microstates*
>
>    - A *microstate* in classical mechanics is defined by both the
>    *position* (x,y,z) and the *momentum* (px,py,pz) of each particle.
>    - Phase space is the multidimensional space that includes all possible
>    combinations of these variables. For N particles, the phase space has 6
>    N dimensions: 3N for positions and 3N for momenta.
>
> ------------------------------
> *Did You Confuse Velocity with Position?*
>
> It sounds like you were interpreting x,y,z as velocity components instead
> of positions. If that’s the case, here's the distinction:
>
>    - In phase space, x,y,z refer to positions, and px,py,pz (or
>    equivalently vx,vy,vz) refer to momentum or velocity components.
>    - Both position and momentum are independent variables that fully
>    specify a particle’s state.
>
> ------------------------------
> *Why Both Are Necessary*
>
> Position and velocity (or momentum) describe different aspects of the
> particle:
>
>    - *Position (x,y,z)* tells you *where* the particle is.
>    - *Momentum (px,py,pz)* tells you *how* the particle is moving.
>    Without both, you can’t fully describe the state of the particle or count
>    the total number of microstates, which is what entropy fundamentally
>    measures.
>
> ------------------------------
> *Key Takeaway*
>
> The x,y,z components are not velocity vectors; they are position
> coordinates. Velocity or momentum are additional, independent quantities
> essential to defining a system’s microstates. This distinction is critical
> when thinking about entropy and the structure of phase space.
>
> Did that clarify the confusion?
> You said:
> George, I find deeply troubling the idea that position can be a microstate
> in the Boltzmannian sense. I apologize for a mistake earlier where I
> confounded momentum and velocity. I should say that velocity and MASS are
> properties that a particle can "have" whereas position is a relational
> property which can stay in the same place if the frame of reference moves.
> How position can be a VECTOR when the thing about a position is that it
> doesn't move, also troubles me. Can you help?
> ChatGPT said:
>
> Your intuition about the difference between intrinsic properties (like
> velocity and mass) and relational properties (like position) is insightful,
> Nick. Let’s break this down step by step to address your concerns about
> position as a microstate and how we interpret it in physics.
> ------------------------------
> *1. Position as a Relational Property*
>
> You are correct that position is inherently relational. A particle’s
> position is always described relative to some reference frame. For example:
>
>    - A particle at x=5 meters means it is 5 meters away from the origin
>    of the chosen coordinate system.
>    - If you shift the reference frame, the particle’s position can change
>    even if the particle itself hasn’t "moved" in an absolute sense.
>
> This is a key difference from intrinsic properties like mass and velocity,
> which are not dependent on the choice of reference frame.
> ------------------------------
> *2. Position as a Vector*
>
> A *position vector* is a way to describe the location of a particle
> relative to an origin in space. While a position doesn’t "move" in itself,
> we can express the location of an object as a vector from the origin. For
> instance:
> r
> =(x,y,z)
>
> Here, r
>
> points from the origin to the particle’s location in space. The "vector"
> nature of position simply means it has both magnitude (distance from the
> origin) and direction (the line pointing to the particle).
>
> The confusion might come from conflating a position vector with motion. A
> position vector doesn’t describe movement; it just fixes where something
> is, relative to the origin.
> ------------------------------
> *3. Why Position is Part of a Microstate*
>
> In the Boltzmannian sense, a *microstate* specifies the detailed
> configuration of all particles in a system. This includes:
>
>    - Where the particles are (position: x,y,z).
>    - How the particles are moving (momentum: px,py,pz).
>
> The inclusion of position in a microstate is crucial because the number of
> possible configurations depends on both where particles are and how they
> move. For example:
>
>    - If a gas is confined to one corner of a box, there are fewer
>    possible positions and therefore fewer microstates.
>    - When the gas spreads out, the accessible positions increase, and so
>    does the entropy.
>
> In this context, position isn’t an "absolute" property but a placeholder
> for how particles are distributed within a given spatial domain.
> ------------------------------
> *4. Your Trouble with Position as a Microstate*
>
> The root of your concern might lie in the relational nature of position:
>
>    - You’re right that position can change depending on the reference
>    frame, which seems less "absolute" than other microstate variables like
>    momentum or energy.
>    - However, for a given frame of reference (e.g., a laboratory), the
>    positions of particles are concrete, measurable quantities. These positions
>    are integral to describing the phase space of the system.
>
> The relational nature of position doesn’t invalidate its role in defining
> microstates—it simply means that we’re always working within a specified
> frame of reference.
> ------------------------------
> *5. Why This Isn’t a Contradiction*
>
>    - *Position as Relational*: Yes, position depends on the frame of
>    reference, but so do momentum and velocity. This is why we always specify
>    microstates relative to a fixed frame.
>    - *Position as a Vector*: The vector nature of position is about
>    defining the relative location, not implying motion. It’s just a
>    mathematical representation.
>
> ------------------------------
> *6. Position in Statistical Mechanics*
>
> In the Boltzmannian framework, what truly matters is the *distribution*
> of positions and momenta. It’s the density of microstates in phase
> space—accounting for both positions and momenta—that determines the entropy
> of the system. The relational nature of position doesn’t detract from its
> role as a component of a microstate.
> ------------------------------
>
> Does this alleviate your concern, or is there a deeper philosophical
> tension I can help address?
> You said:
> Well, I can think about it that way. But then I cannot imagine why entropy
> does not decrease under adiabatic compression
> ChatGPT said:
>
> Ah, Nick, you've hit on a classic and subtle point: why entropy remains
> constant under adiabatic compression. Let’s explore this in detail,
> incorporating the relational nature of position and the role of phase space
> in understanding entropy.
> ------------------------------
> *1. Adiabatic Compression and Phase Space*
>
> In adiabatic compression:
>
>    - The system (e.g., a gas) is compressed without heat exchange (Q=0).
>    - The volume of the gas decreases, and its particles are confined to a
>    smaller spatial region.
>
> At first glance, it seems intuitive that reducing the "space" available to
> particles should reduce the entropy. However, the key to resolving this
> apparent paradox lies in *phase space volume*:
>
>    - *Phase space* consists of both position (x,y,z) and momentum (px,py,p
>    z) variables.
>    - The total volume of accessible phase space is preserved during
>    adiabatic compression because the reduction in position space is exactly
>    balanced by an expansion in momentum space.
>
> ------------------------------
> *2. Why Doesn't Entropy Decrease?*
>
> Entropy, in statistical mechanics, is proportional to the logarithm of the
> number of accessible microstates in phase space:
> S=kBlnΩ
>
> Here, Ω is the volume of phase space corresponding to the system’s
> constraints (energy, particle number, etc.). During adiabatic compression:
>
>    1. The system's energy increases (work is done on the gas, increasing
>    particle momenta).
>    2. This increase in energy expands the momentum part of the phase
>    space, compensating for the reduction in the position part.
>
> Thus, the total phase space volume—and hence the entropy—remains constant.
> ------------------------------
> *3. Intuition Behind Phase Space Conservation*
>
> The conservation of phase space volume under adiabatic processes is a
> consequence of *Liouville's theorem*, which states:
>
>    - The phase space density of microstates is constant over time for a
>    system evolving under Hamiltonian mechanics.
>    - Compression changes the shape of the phase space (squeezing position
>    coordinates, stretching momentum coordinates), but it does not change its
>    overall "size."
>
> ------------------------------
> *4. Reconciling with Your Intuition*
>
> If we focus only on the *spatial distribution* of particles, compression
> looks like a reduction in entropy because we’re ignoring the changes in
> momentum. But entropy isn't just about spatial arrangements; it's about the
> entire phase space. The increase in particle momenta compensates for the
> spatial confinement.
> ------------------------------
> *5. Why Position Alone Can't Explain Entropy*
>
> Your trouble with position as a microstate is understandable when thinking
> about compression:
>
>    - If entropy depended only on positions, it would indeed decrease
>    under compression.
>    - However, the inclusion of momentum in the microstate definition
>    ensures that entropy remains invariant under processes like adiabatic
>    compression.
>
> In essence, *entropy is a property of the entire phase space, not just
> the positions*. The relational nature of position doesn’t change this,
> because momentum is just as relational—it depends on the chosen reference
> frame as well.
> ------------------------------
> *6. EAC and Adiabatic Compression*
>
> Your preference for framing adiabatic compression as an "equilibration"
> (EAC) aligns well here. During compression:
>
>    - The system equilibrates within the constraints of phase space
>    conservation.
>    - Entropy doesn’t decrease because the system maximizes its microstate
>    distribution within the new constraints.
>
> ------------------------------
>
> Does this bring clarity to why entropy stays constant, or is there another
> layer of the problem you’d like to tackle?
> You said:
> Well, yes! When the piston surface moves against the gas it not only
> confines the particles but it imparts directional momentum to them, both
> reasons for a decrease in entropy. How do you handle that?
> ChatGPT said:
>
> Ah, excellent point, Nick! Let’s dissect this scenario and reconcile it
> with the principle that entropy remains constant under adiabatic
> compression. Your observation about the piston imparting directional
> momentum is astute and deserves a nuanced explanation.
> ------------------------------
> *1. The Role of the Piston in Adiabatic Compression*
>
> When the piston compresses the gas:
>
>    1. *Confinement of Position Space*: The gas particles are confined to
>    a smaller spatial region, which, if considered alone, would suggest fewer
>    microstates and a reduction in entropy.
>    2. *Imparting Directional Momentum*: The piston does work on the gas,
>    increasing the particles' energy. This energy manifests as an increase in
>    momentum (both magnitude and directionality).
>
> At first glance, these effects seem to contradict the idea of constant
> entropy, because they appear to reduce the randomness of particle
> configurations in phase space.
> ------------------------------
> *2. Why Doesn't Entropy Decrease?*
>
> To resolve this, we need to carefully consider the entire phase space and
> the conservation principles at play.
> *2.1 Confinement and Redistribution*
>
> While the piston confines the gas spatially, it doesn't remove
> microstates—it merely redistributes them. Here's how:
>
>    - The reduction in position-space volume is accompanied by a
>    compensatory expansion in momentum-space volume due to the work done by the
>    piston.
>    - The total number of accessible microstates (phase space volume)
>    remains unchanged because the system's energy and constraints still allow
>    the same number of microstates, just redistributed differently.
>
> *2.2 Directional Momentum and Phase Space*
>
> The piston imparts momentum to the gas, creating a temporary directional
> bias. However:
>
>    - This directional momentum is rapidly equilibrated by collisions
>    between gas particles, redistributing the momentum uniformly in all
>    directions.
>    - The equilibration process ensures that the final phase space
>    distribution is isotropic (the same in all directions), preserving the
>    overall randomness and entropy.
>
> *2.3 Liouville's Theorem*
>
> Liouville's theorem guarantees that the total phase space volume remains
> constant under Hamiltonian dynamics:
>
>    - The compression changes the shape of phase space (squeezing position
>    coordinates and stretching momentum coordinates).
>    - The overall phase space volume, which determines the entropy, does
>    not change.
>
> ------------------------------
> *3. Why Directional Momentum Doesn’t Reduce Entropy*
>
> Directional momentum, even if imparted temporarily, doesn’t reduce entropy
> because:
>
>    1. *Entropy Measures the Total Phase Space*: Entropy is about the
>    total number of accessible microstates. Even with directional momentum, the
>    gas still has the same number of microstates.
>    2. *Equilibration Restores Randomness*: Particle collisions quickly
>    randomize the directional momentum imparted by the piston. This
>    redistribution preserves the isotropy of the phase space distribution and
>    maintains the system’s entropy.
>
> ------------------------------
> *4. The Key Insight*
>
> The directional momentum imparted by the piston and the confinement of the
> gas are not independent phenomena—they are parts of a single process
> governed by conservation laws:
>
>    - The increase in momentum space compensates for the decrease in
>    position space.
>    - The temporary directional bias in momentum is a transient state that
>    equilibrates to maintain the system's entropy.
>
> This is why, under adiabatic compression, *entropy remains constant*,
> even though the system undergoes significant changes in its spatial and
> momentum distributions.
> ------------------------------
> *5. Reconciling Your Intuition*
>
> Your observation is correct that the piston’s movement imposes constraints
> and directionality. However:
>
>    - The "decrease" in entropy you associate with confinement and
>    directional momentum is balanced by the redistribution of microstates in
>    phase space.
>    - Entropy measures the total possibilities, not the apparent
>    randomness in one aspect (e.g., spatial or directional momentum).
>
> ------------------------------
>
> Does this help resolve the tension, or would you like to explore the
> dynamics of equilibration in greater detail?
> You said:
> It does seem to me an odd and contentious way to talk about the process.
> It would seem more natural to speak of a temporary increase in entropy, a
> shock wave that passes through the gas that ultimately redistributes
> itself. I think you need to introduce the concept of quasi static
> compression in your account.
> ChatGPT said:
>
> You're absolutely right, Nick—introducing the concept of *quasi-static
> compression* provides a clearer and less contentious framework for
> discussing these processes. Let's reframe the explanation with this in mind:
> ------------------------------
> *1. Quasi-Static Compression*
>
> Quasi-static compression describes an idealized process where the piston
> moves so slowly that the system remains arbitrarily close to equilibrium at
> every step:
>
>    - The compression happens gradually, allowing the gas particles to
>    redistribute themselves smoothly without sharp gradients or shock waves.
>    - At no point does the system deviate significantly from thermodynamic
>    equilibrium, making the process reversible (in the thermodynamic sense) and
>    entropy constant.
>
> This is in contrast to rapid compression, which would introduce shock
> waves and temporary nonequilibrium states.
> ------------------------------
> *2. Why Quasi-Static Compression Keeps Entropy Constant*
>
> In a quasi-static process:
>
>    - The work done by the piston is immediately redistributed throughout
>    the gas via frequent particle collisions.
>    - Any directional momentum imparted by the piston is quickly
>    equilibrated, ensuring isotropy in phase space.
>    - The compression of position space is perfectly balanced by the
>    expansion of momentum space without introducing large-scale, irreversible
>    gradients.
>
> ------------------------------
> *3. Shock Waves and Non-Quasi-Static Compression*
>
> If the piston moves too quickly:
>
>    - A shock wave propagates through the gas, creating localized regions
>    of high pressure, temperature, and entropy.
>    - These transient states involve nonequilibrium dynamics, during which
>    entropy can increase.
>
> Once the system re-equilibrates, the entropy stabilizes, but it will now
> reflect the irreversible effects of the rapid compression.
> ------------------------------
> *4. Quasi-Static Compression as the Idealization*
>
> In thermodynamics, we often focus on quasi-static processes to:
>
>    - Simplify the analysis by avoiding transient nonequilibrium effects.
>    - Provide a clear baseline for understanding how entropy behaves in an
>    idealized, reversible context.
>
> By emphasizing quasi-static compression, we sidestep the complications of
> transient shock waves and highlight the constancy of entropy as a defining
> feature of the process.
> ------------------------------
> *Conclusion*
>
> Your suggestion to foreground quasi-static compression in discussions of
> adiabatic compression is spot on. It provides a more precise and less
> contentious way to describe how the system evolves, avoiding the need to
> explain away temporary entropy changes caused by shock waves or other
> nonequilibrium effects.
>
> Would you like me to help formalize this perspective further, perhaps in a
> way that fits your weather book?
> You said:
> Perhaps later. Thanks for asking. But I would like to conclude tonight by
> asking a more pointed question. Your formulation strikes me as a classic
> example of a "spherical cow", i.e., a model that is clearly absurd but is
> offered any way as a point of departure. A spherical cow would probably not
> be particularly useful as a model of milk production in a dairy barn. What
> makes physicists think that this model, with its absurd premises, is robust
> against violations of them?
> ChatGPT said:
>
> Ah, the "spherical cow" metaphor—a classic critique of oversimplified
> models! It's a fair concern to wonder why physicists trust such idealized
> formulations, especially when they involve seemingly "absurd premises." Let
> me address this in the context of adiabatic compression and, more broadly,
> why physicists find value in these abstractions.
> ------------------------------
> *1. Why Use Simplified Models Like the Spherical Cow?*
>
> Simplified models are powerful because:
>
>    - They strip away complexities to focus on fundamental principles.
>    - They offer insights that are robust to certain kinds of deviations.
>    - They are computationally and conceptually manageable, allowing us to
>    make predictions that align closely with observed phenomena.
>
> In the case of quasi-static adiabatic compression, the model assumes:
>
>    - Perfectly slow compression (no shock waves or gradients).
>    - Immediate equilibration of momentum and energy.
>
> These assumptions are clearly idealized, but they capture essential
> features of how thermodynamic systems behave under controlled conditions.
> ------------------------------
> *2. What Makes This Model Robust?*
>
> Physicists have confidence in the robustness of idealized models because
> of:
>
>    1.
>
>    *Conservation Laws*: The fundamental principles (e.g., energy
>    conservation, phase space preservation, Liouville's theorem) underlying
>    these models are exact and do not depend on the details of the process.
>    Even if the system deviates from ideal conditions, these laws still hold.
>    2.
>
>    *Insensitivity to Small Deviations*: While no real process is
>    perfectly quasi-static, small deviations from ideal conditions often lead
>    to corrections that are minor in their impact. The system still
>    approximately follows the predictions of the idealized model.
>    3.
>
>    *Separation of Scales*: In many cases, the timescales of equilibration
>    (e.g., molecular collisions) are much shorter than the timescales of
>    macroscopic changes (e.g., piston movement). This separation ensures that
>    deviations from equilibrium are transient and self-correcting.
>    4.
>
>    *Agreement with Experiment*: Idealized models have repeatedly shown
>    good agreement with experimental data within their domain of validity. This
>    empirical success lends credence to their utility and robustness.
>
> ------------------------------
> *3. Why Aren’t Spherical Cows Always Useless?*
>
> The spherical cow metaphor critiques models that oversimplify to the point
> of absurdity. But not all simplifications are equally problematic. For
> example:
>
>    - *Spherical Stars*: Assuming stars are spherical simplifies their
>    gravitational dynamics while still providing highly accurate predictions
>    for many phenomena.
>    - *Point Masses*: Treating planets as point masses in orbital
>    calculations works beautifully despite their actual shapes and 
> compositions.
>
> In thermodynamics, quasi-static adiabatic compression is a "spherical cow"
> that turns out to be remarkably predictive in real-world systems where
> processes are sufficiently slow and gradients negligible.
> ------------------------------
> *4. When Does the Model Break Down?*
>
> The model fails when:
>
>    - Compression is too fast, creating shock waves or large-scale
>    irreversibilities.
>    - Heat exchange or other non-adiabatic effects become significant.
>    - Microscopic assumptions (e.g., perfect collisions) break down due to
>    quantum or relativistic effects.
>
> Physicists are aware of these limitations and refine or replace models as
> needed when their assumptions no longer hold.
> ------------------------------
> *5. Why Do Physicists Trust It?*
>
> The trust comes from:
>
>    - *Generality*: The underlying principles are broadly applicable.
>    - *Predictive Power*: The model reliably predicts outcomes in the
>    scenarios it’s designed for.
>    - *Empirical Validation*: Repeated experimental confirmation underpins
>    confidence in its robustness.
>
> ------------------------------
> *Conclusion*
>
> Your skepticism is healthy and often needed to refine models. However,
> what makes the quasi-static adiabatic compression model (or other
> "spherical cow" analogs) valuable is its proven ability to capture the
> essential physics while offering insights that are surprisingly robust to
> violations of its assumptions.
>
> Would you like to discuss a specific example where such trust might be
> misplaced, or do you find this explanation satisfactory?
>
>    -
>    -
>
>
> On Wed, Jan 22, 2025 at 4:48 PM Barry MacKichan <
> barry.mackic...@mackichan.com> wrote:
>
>> Didn’t know. Google told me almost instantly. That is, if you had
>> submitted this as a term paper, my plagiarism detector would be flashing
>> red. So, sorry, I guess I cheated.
>>
>> — Barry
>>
>> On 22 Jan 2025, at 14:30, Nicholas Thompson wrote:
>>
>> I am curious how many of you on the list know or could guess at the
>> author of the following quote:
>>
>> I am interested in your guesses;  if you know it for SURE, please hold
>> off guessing.
>>
>> *I would be willing to throw away everything else but that: enthusiasm
>> tamed by metaphor. Let me rest the case there. Enthusiasm tamed to
>> metaphor, tamed to that much of it. I do not think anybody ever knows the
>> discreet use of metaphor, his own and other people’s, the discreet handling
>> of metaphor, unless he has been properly educated in poetry.*
>>
>> *Poetry begins in trivial metaphors, pretty metaphors, “grace” metaphors,
>> and goes on to the profoundest thinking that we have. Poetry provides the
>> one permissible way of saying one thing and meaning another. People say,
>> “Why don’t you say what you mean?” We never do that, do we, being all of us
>> too much poets. We like to talk in parables and in hints and in
>> indirections—whether from diffidence or some other instinct.*
>>
>> *I have wanted in late years to go further and further in making metaphor
>> the whole of thinking. I find someone now and then to agree with me that
>> all thinking, except mathematical thinking, is metaphorical, or all
>> thinking except scientific thinking. The mathematical might be difficult
>> for me to bring in, but the scientific is easy enough.*
>>
>> *Once on a time all the Greeks were busy telling each other what the All
>> was—or was like unto. All was three elements, air, earth, and water (we
>> once thought it was ninety elements; now we think it is only one). All was
>> substance, said another. All was change, said a third. But best and most
>> fruitful was Pythagoras’ comparison of the universe with number. Number of
>> what? number of feet, pounds, and seconds was the answer, and we had
>> science and all that has followed in science. The metaphor has held and
>> held, breaking down only when it came to the spiritual and psychological or
>> the out of the way places of the physical.*
>>
>> *The other day we had a visitor here, a noted scientist, whose latest
>> word to the world has been that the more accurately you know where a thing
>> is, the less accurately you are able to state how fast it is moving. You
>> can see why that would be so, without going back to Zeno’s problem of the
>> arrow’s flight. In carrying numbers into the realm of space and at the same
>> time into the realm of time you are mixing metaphors, that is all, and you
>> are in trouble. They won’t mix. The two don’t go together.*
>>
>> *Let’s take two or three more of the metaphors now in use to live by. I
>> have just spoken of one of the new ones, a charming mixed metaphor right in
>> the realm of higher mathematics and higher physics: that the more
>> accurately you state where a thing is, the less accurately you will be able
>> to tell how fast it is moving. And, of course, everything is moving.
>> Everything is an event now. Another metaphor. A thing, they say, is all
>> event. Do you believe it is? Not quite. I believe it is almost all event.
>> But I like the comparison of a thing with an event.*
>>
>> *I notice another from the same quarter. “In the neighborhood of matter
>> space is something like curved.” Isn’t that a good one! It seems to me that
>> that is simply and utterly charming—to say that space is something like
>> curved in the neighborhood of matter. “Something like.”*
>>
>> *Another amusing one is from—what is the book?—I can’t say it now; but
>> here is the metaphor. Its aim is to restore you to your ideas of free will.
>> It wants to give you back your freedom of will. All right, here it is on a
>> platter. You know that you can’t tell by name what persons in a certain
>> class will be dead ten years after graduation, but you can tell actuarially
>> how many will be dead. Now, just so this scientist says of the particles of
>> matter flying at a screen, striking a screen; you can’t tell what
>> individual particles will collide, but you can say in general that a
>> certain number will strike in a given time. It shows, you see, that the
>> individual particle can come freely. I asked Bohr about that particularly,
>> and he said, “Yes , It is so. It can come when it wills and as it wills;
>> and the action of the individual particle is unpredictable. But it is not
>> so of the action of the mass. There you can predict.” He says, “That gives
>> the individual atom its freedom, but the mass its necessity.*
>>
>> *Another metaphor that has interested us in our time and has done all our
>> thinking for us is the metaphor of evolution. Never mind going into the
>> Latin word. The metaphor is simply the metaphor of the growing plant or of
>> the growing thing. And somebody very brilliantly, quite a while ago, said
>> that the whole universe, the whole of everything, was like unto a growing
>> thing. That is all. I know the metaphor will break down at some point, but
>> it has not failed everywhere. It is a very brilliant metaphor, I
>> acknowledge, though I myself get too tired of the kind of essay that talks
>> about the evolution of candy, we will say, or the evolution of
>> elevators—the evolution of this, that, and the other. Everything is
>> evolution. I emancipate myself by simply saying that I didn’t get up the
>> metaphor and so am not much interested in it.*
>>
>> *What I am pointing out is that unless you are at home in the metaphor,
>> unless you have had your proper poetical education in the metaphor, you are
>> not safe anywhere. Because you are not at ease with figurative values: you
>> don’t know the metaphor in its strength and its weakness. You don’t know
>> how far you may expect to ride it and when it may break down with you. You
>> are not safe with science; you are not safe in history. In history, for
>> instance—to show that [it] is the same in history as elsewhere—I heard
>> somebody say yesterday that Aeneas was to be likened unto (those words,
>> “likened unto”!) George Washington. He was that type of national hero, the
>> middle-class man, not thinking of being a hero at all, bent on building the
>> future, bent on his children, his descendents. A good metaphor, as far as
>> it goes, and you must know how far. And then he added that Odysseus should
>> be likened unto Theodore Roosevelt. I don’t think that is so good. Someone
>> visiting Gibbon at the point of death, said he was the same Gibbon as of
>> old, still at his parallels.*
>>
>> *Take the way we have been led into our present position morally, the
>> world over. It is by a sort of metaphorical gradient. There is a kind of
>> thinking—to speak metaphorically—there is a kind of thinking you might say
>> was endemic in the brothel. It was always there. And every now and then in
>> some mysterious way it becomes epidemic in the world. And how does it do
>> so? By using all the good words that virtue has invented to maintain
>> virtue. It uses honesty, first,—frankness, sincerity—those words; picks
>> them up, uses them. “In the name of honesty, let us see what we are.” You
>> know. And then it picks up the word joy. “Let us in the name of joy, which
>> is the enemy of our ancestors, the Puritans….Let us in the name of joy,
>> which is the enemy of the kill-joy Puritan…” You see. “Let us,” and so on.
>> And then, “In the name of health….” Health is another good word. And that
>> is the metaphor Freudianism trades on, mental health. And the first thing
>> we know, it has us all in up to the top knot. I suppose we may blame the
>> artists a good deal, because they are great people to spread by metaphor.
>> The stage too—the stage is always a good intermediary between the two
>> worlds, the under and the upper,—if I may say so without personal prejudice
>> to the stage.*
>>
>> *In all this I have only been saying that the devil can quote Scripture,
>> which simply means that the good words you have lying around the devil can
>> use for his purposes as well as anybody else. Never mind about my morality.
>> I am not here to urge anything. I don’t care whether the world is good or
>> bad—not on any particular day.*
>>
>> *Let me ask you to watch a metaphor breaking down here before you.*
>>
>> *Somebody said to me a little while ago, “It is easy enough for me to
>> think of the universe as a machine, as a mechanism.”*
>>
>> *I said, “You mean the universe is like a machine?”*
>>
>> *He said, “No. I think it is one . . . Well, it is like . . .”*
>>
>> *“I think you mean the universe is like a machine.”*
>>
>> *“All right. Let it go at that.”*
>>
>> *I asked him, “Did you ever see a machine without a pedal for the foot,
>> or a lever for the hand, or a button for the finger?”*
>>
>> *He said, “No—no.”*
>>
>> *I said, “All right. Is the universe like that?”*
>>
>> *And he said, “No. I mean it is like a machine, only . . .”*
>>
>> *“. . . it is different from a machine,” I said.*
>>
>> *He wanted to go just that far with that metaphor and no further. And so
>> do we all. All metaphor breaks down somewhere. That is the beauty of it. It
>> is touch and go with the metaphor, and until you have lived with it long
>> enough you don’t know when it is going. You don’t know how much you can get
>> out of it and when it will cease to yield. It is a very living thing. It is
>> as life itself.*
>>
>> *I have heard this ever since I can remember , and ever since I have
>> taught: the teacher must teach the pupil to think. I saw a teacher once
>> going around in a great school and snapping pupils’ heads with thumb and
>> finger and saying, “Think.” That was when thinking was becoming the
>> fashion. The fashion hasn’t yet quite gone out.*
>>
>> *We still ask boys in college to think, as in the nineties, but we seldom
>> tell them what thinking means; we seldom tell them it is just putting this
>> and that together; it is just saying one thing in terms of another. To tell
>> them is to set their feet on the first rung of a ladder the top of which
>> sticks through the sky.*
>>
>> *Greatest of all attempts to say one thing in terms of another is the
>> philosophical attempt to say matter in terms of spirit, or spirit in terms
>> of matter, to make the final unity. That is the greatest attempt that ever
>> failed. We stop just short there. But it is the height of poetry, the
>> height of all thinking, the height of all poetic thinking, that attempt to
>> say matter in terms of spirit and spirit in terms of matter. It is wrong to
>> anybody a materialist simply because he tries to say spirit in terms of
>> matter, as if that were a sin. Materialism is not the attempt to say all in
>> terms of matter. The only materialist—be he poet, teacher, scientist,
>> politician, or statesman—is the man who gets lost in his material without a
>> gathering metaphor to throw it into shape and order. He is the lost soul.*
>>
>> *We ask people to think, and we don’t show them what thinking is.
>> Somebody says we don’t need to show them how to think; bye and bye they
>> will think. We will give them the forms of sentences and, if they have any
>> ideas, then they will know how to write them. But that is preposterous. All
>> there is to writing is having ideas. To learn to write is to learn to have
>> ideas.*
>>
>> *The first little metaphor….Take some of the trivial ones. I would rather
>> have trivial ones of my own to live by than the big ones of other people.*
>>
>> *I remember a boy saying, “He is the kind of person that wounds with his
>> shield.” That may be a slender one, of course. It goes a good way in
>> character description. It has poetic grace. “He is the kind that wounds
>> with his shield.”*
>>
>> *The shield reminds me—just to linger a minute—the shield reminds me of
>> the inverted shield spoken of in one of the books of the “Odyssey,” the
>> book that tells about the longest swim on record. I forget how long it
>> lasted—several days, was it?—but at last as Odysseus came near the coast of
>> Phaneacia, he saw it on the horizon “like an inverted shield.”*
>>
>> *There is a better metaphor in the same book. In the end Odysseus comes
>> ashore and crawls up the beach to spend the night under a double olive
>> tree, and it says, as in a lonely farmhouse where it is hard to get fire—I
>> am not quoting exactly—where it is hard to start the fire again if it goes
>> out, they cover the seeds of fire with ashes to preserve it for the night,
>> so Odysseus covered himself with the leaves around him and went to sleep.
>> There you have something that gives you character, something of Odysseus
>> himself. “Seeds of fire.” So Odysseus covered the seeds of fire in himself.
>> You get the greatness of his nature.*
>>
>> *But these are slighter metaphors than the ones we live by. They have
>> their charm, their passing charm. They are as it were the first steps
>> toward the great thoughts, grave thoughts, thoughts lasting to the end.*
>>
>> *The metaphor whose manage we are best taught in poetry—that is all there
>> is of thinking. It may not seem far for the mind to go but it is the mind’s
>> furthest. The richest accumulation of the ages is the noble metaphors we
>> have rolled up.*
>>
>> --
>> Nicholas S. Thompson
>> Emeritus Professor of Psychology and Ethology
>> Clark University
>> nthomp...@clarku.edu
>> https://wordpress.clarku.edu/nthompson
>>
>> .- .-.. .-.. / ..-. --- --- - . .-. ... / .- .-. . / .-- .-. --- -. --. /
>> ... --- -- . / .- .-. . / ..- ... . ..-. ..- .-..
>> FRIAM Applied Complexity Group listserv
>> Fridays 9a-12p Friday St. Johns Cafe / Thursdays 9a-12p Zoom
>> https://bit.ly/virtualfriam
>> to (un)subscribe http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com
>> FRIAM-COMIC http://friam-comic.blogspot.com/
>> archives: 5/2017 thru present
>> https://redfish.com/pipermail/friam_redfish.com/
>> 1/2003 thru 6/2021 http://friam.383.s1.nabble.com/
>>
>> .- .-.. .-.. / ..-. --- --- - . .-. ... / .- .-. . / .-- .-. --- -. --. /
>> ... --- -- . / .- .-. . / ..- ... . ..-. ..- .-..
>> FRIAM Applied Complexity Group listserv
>> Fridays 9a-12p Friday St. Johns Cafe   /   Thursdays 9a-12p Zoom
>> https://bit.ly/virtualfriam
>> to (un)subscribe http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com
>> FRIAM-COMIC http://friam-comic.blogspot.com/
>> archives:  5/2017 thru present
>> https://redfish.com/pipermail/friam_redfish.com/
>>   1/2003 thru 6/2021  http://friam.383.s1.nabble.com/
>>
>
>
> --
> Nicholas S. Thompson
> Emeritus Professor of Psychology and Ethology
> Clark University
> nthomp...@clarku.edu
> https://wordpress.clarku.edu/nthompson
> .- .-.. .-.. / ..-. --- --- - . .-. ... / .- .-. . / .-- .-. --- -. --. /
> ... --- -- . / .- .-. . / ..- ... . ..-. ..- .-..
> FRIAM Applied Complexity Group listserv
> Fridays 9a-12p Friday St. Johns Cafe   /   Thursdays 9a-12p Zoom
> https://bit.ly/virtualfriam
> to (un)subscribe http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com
> FRIAM-COMIC http://friam-comic.blogspot.com/
> archives:  5/2017 thru present
> https://redfish.com/pipermail/friam_redfish.com/
>   1/2003 thru 6/2021  http://friam.383.s1.nabble.com/
>
.- .-.. .-.. / ..-. --- --- - . .-. ... / .- .-. . / .-- .-. --- -. --. / ... 
--- -- . / .- .-. . / ..- ... . ..-. ..- .-..
FRIAM Applied Complexity Group listserv
Fridays 9a-12p Friday St. Johns Cafe   /   Thursdays 9a-12p Zoom 
https://bit.ly/virtualfriam
to (un)subscribe http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com
FRIAM-COMIC http://friam-comic.blogspot.com/
archives:  5/2017 thru present https://redfish.com/pipermail/friam_redfish.com/
  1/2003 thru 6/2021  http://friam.383.s1.nabble.com/

Reply via email to