A person who works in data compression, randomness, or statistical mechanics 
might try to frame a description that is as operational and contains as much 
structural resolution in it as possible, by drawing language from the sectors 
of behavior and observation that are as robustly disambiguatable among people 
as possible. 
Main originators Kolmogorov (minimum sufficient statistics), Rissanen (minimum 
description length).  It would be about ensembles of the possible, the role of 
the actualized within that ensemble, and whether the actual can be partly 
identified by recognizing smaller ensembles in which it is typical, rather than 
starting with larger ensembles in which it is atypical by some criterion.  A 
description might run something like this:

1. The way the graphic is presented to the viewer (dots moving almost in lines 
on a deliberately blank and flat page) — taking into account that it was 
designed by people to make a point when viewed by people — suggests an ensemble 
in which the dots could be positioned anywhere (formalized in some model of 
randomness) and could over time trace any trajectory of their joint motion 
defined by nearly linear (inertial-looking) intervals with certain occasional 
nearly-angular reflections.

2. It happens that the actual trajectory of positions does not have nearly so 
much freedom.  It can be defined by maintaining four equilateral triangles the 
centroids of which are positioned on a rotating square, and the orientations of 
which rotate at a particular rate relative to the rotation rate of the square.  
I don’t see right away whether there is some important relation between the two 
rotation rates re. tracing out the prism, or whether any ratio of the two 
rotation rates in some interval would produce a prism with the same topological 
properties and only different relative areas of the internal triangular panels. 
 (I suspect the latter, and also that if I weren’t so lazy, that would be easy 
to prove.)  It would be a little more interesting if some relative rotation 
rates produce “the most random-looking” motions of the dots, and in that way 
some combinations are special for their ability to fool the viewer by mimicking 
the usual computational models of random-ideal-gases-in-boxes.

3.  The specification of any trajectory within an ensemble of possible motions 
constrained as in point 2 is vastly shorter, involving only positions and sizes 
of four triangles, and two rotation rates, than the specification of a 
particular trajectory within an ensemble that allows any “random” trajectories 
in the collection suggested in point 1.  Although several different-looking 
patterns can be drawn on the resulting dots (only triangles, only squares, or 
only the prism), these patterns do not have fully independent information.  
Each is a _function_ (mathematical sense) of the minimal information set 
identifying the trajectory, meaning that it adds no new information to what is 
already in that minimal set.  The fact that, if we draw triangles, we have four 
of them in a square, whereas if we draw squares, we have three of them on an 
equilateral, is a visual illustration that the same constraints are being 
expressed in either rendering.

My above list did not use the word “real”.  The operational description 
contained no role for an “observer”; it consists of defined relations of 
smaller ensembles within larger ones.  To the extent that there was any 
“observer” in the language, that was in the framing narrative that defends our 
choice to introduce ensemble 1 as an a priori model, based on claims of how 
people set up optical illusions and games to illustrate things to other people. 
 Whether or not that framing narrative is correct has no bearing on whether the 
ensembles _can_ be defined, or on our ability to state true propositions about 
relations between the sub-ensemble 2, the prior ensemble 1, and the specificity 
of the actual trajectory within either of them.  The various information 
measures in the ensembles do not depend on whether we choose to draw lines in 
the graphic to express different variable values in rendering the trajectory; 
that choice governs the interface between the properties of the ensemble and 
the consumption propensities of people looking at computer graphics, and could 
be considered to occupy a conversation in cognition and neuroscience.


I just got out of a starting conversational exchange with a philosopher of 
science who writes about emergence, and it has the same unhappy and inter-human 
fraught tenor as my above paragraphs.  Apologies for that.  I try to understand 
what ontologists believe their language carries, which is not carried in the 
more nuts-and-bolts language that they generally know but don’t think needs to 
be part of the discussion.  If we believed ourselves to be discussing the 
structure, oddities, and hazards of human perspective-taking, I could see their 
language as having descriptive value in that realm, but I think they believe it 
is not “only” that, but actually not that “at all”.  I think they are saying 
they are saying something else.  

I suppose what I am supposed to do is not worry about whether there are 
operational, structured languages enabling us to see clearly and speak 
systematically about what the dots might do versus what they do, and rather 
view the whole exercise as a metaphor whose elements are meant to stand in for 
some other relations in the ways we try to use conversation or choreographed 
behavior to arrive at something with reliability properties beyond those of our 
shifting and ephemeral perceptive gestalts.  Or maybe not that at all, and 
something completely different was supposed to be the point….

Eric



> On Jan 13, 2019, at 4:23 AM, Nick Thompson <nickthomp...@earthlink.net> wrote:
> 
> Wow.  It's all those things at once!  
>  
> REALLY?!!!!!
>  
> What a great example!
>  
> Let me try and put it into words.  The nominalist would like to say “There is 
> no real pattern there, it just depends on how you want to look at it.”  The 
> realist would like to say, “Nonsense.  The patterns appear when you take into 
> account the point of view of the observer.  Anybody who cares to take that 
> point of view, adopt that procedure, etc., will see each pattern.  They are 
> real patterns.”  
>  
> How do you understand it, Dave? 
>  
> Nick
>  
> Nicholas S. Thompson
> Emeritus Professor of Psychology and Biology
> Clark University
> http://home.earthlink.net/~nickthompson/naturaldesigns/
>  
>  
> -----Original Message-----
> From: Friam [mailto:friam-boun...@redfish.com] On Behalf Of Prof David West
> Sent: Saturday, January 12, 2019 11:53 AM
> To: friam@redfish.com
> Subject: [FRIAM] models, reality, etc.
>  
> This popped up elsewhere and I thought the FRIAM group might find it 
> interesting. I had not heard of "statistical equivalence" before. The GIF 
> recalled to mind previous conversations about Reality (which is "real:" the 
> dots, the triangles, the squares, ...?); models; interpretations (ala 
> Copenhagen); even Nick's Natural Design.
>  
> davew
> ============================================================
> FRIAM Applied Complexity Group listserv
> Meets Fridays 9a-11:30 at cafe at St. John's College
> to unsubscribe http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com
> archives back to 2003: http://friam.471366.n2.nabble.com/
> FRIAM-COMIC http://friam-comic.blogspot.com/ by Dr. Strangelove


============================================================
FRIAM Applied Complexity Group listserv
Meets Fridays 9a-11:30 at cafe at St. John's College
to unsubscribe http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com
archives back to 2003: http://friam.471366.n2.nabble.com/
FRIAM-COMIC http://friam-comic.blogspot.com/ by Dr. Strangelove

Reply via email to