How do we trust bits to represent money? Someone asked this (Mike Rosing, I think it was).
I argue that the question is, as stated, not well-grounded at this time. No one is asking for bits to be trusted, from first principles, absent real products and a real embedding in a financial system. Perhaps in N years, when Chaum/Brands kinds of digital money are actually being used, such a question will be more meaningful. Then we can ask Mary Jones why she trusts that the numbers being sent between her smart card or computer to her bank or moneychanger are really trustable. Until then, asking Mary why she should trust bits as money is inappropriate. However, even then, in N years, the question will be problematic. Consider this: we 'trust" bits flowing between credit card verifiers, banks, and vendors. And we trust the welter of bits flowing in and amongst computers handling bank accounts, checks, traveller's checks, international clearing houses, SWIFT, etc. None of these systems are handling "money" in anything but a bookkeeping or accounting sense. Money is marks. Trust. Trust is a misleading concept. I recommend (and have done so for a long time...this is not new) doing a coordinate shift and recasting discussions about "trust" into discussions about "belief." * At a very early age most children learn that the coins given to them by their parents may be exchanged for ice cream cones and rides on ponies. (Or for vials of crack, translating this experience into the inner cities.) Do they "trust" that a quarter is "really" a quarter, or is really money? No, they merely have an _expectation_, a _belief_, that the future will continue to look very much like the past and that the quarters in their pocket will very likely, almost with certainty, be accepted by store owners. * At a somewhat later age, most children are introduced to the ideas of bank accounts. Often through school-sponsored Savings Bond programs or passbook savings accounts. (These fell into disfavor during the inflationary 70s.). In any case, children learn to _expect_, to _believe_, that the markings in their passbooks mean that a bank will let them take dollars and quarters out with the appropriate incantations to the bank teller. Whether the money in the bank is real or imaginary is not at issue, only the expectation of a future. * And so on. Nearly all forms of money we encounter in the modern world are based on this pattern that the future will, in most cases, look a lot like the future. When there are exceptions, as with bank failures or frauds, this modifies the belief function. (Children learn, most of them, that lending money to other children and expecting to get it back is much different than depositing/lending money to the Big Bank and expecting to get it back. Children of the 1930s or of Weimar Germany may have suitable tweaks to this model, but the larger point is the same.) Bayesian reasoning, in other words. Experiential learning, with actors/institutions embedded in a larger matrix. The Big Bank is _expected_ to be more reputable, more trustable, because of a bunch of connections it has to other actors, to the past, and to its future. Some of these things we call "reputation" (or "reputation capital"), some we call "trust." But belief is the ultimate fabric, the ultimate currency. We place _bets_ on whether loans will be repaid (risk, loansharking, vigorish, etc.). We _discount_ certain financial instruments based on our expectations or beliefs about the future. Furthermore, the entire "is-a" object model, where "is-a bank" and "has-an account balance of" can and SHOULD (IMO) be replaced with a more realistic and more interesting model of "believes." All of digital money is recastable in terms of Alice believes, Bob believes, Charles believes, etc. All of finance is about belief. (And there are very intriguing semantics of these models. Saul Kripke is one place to look, as he pioneered the "possible worlds semantics" approach. All of human and animal behavior is largely based on building internal models of how the world works, what other people and animals will be doing ("will be doing" in a possible worlds sense), and what the implications of various courses of action will likely be.) We don't "trust" that the sun will rise tomorrow: we _believe_ it will rise, because it has for every day for the past several billion years and we see no causal reason to doubt that 0.9999....947365 of all possible worlds involve the sun coming up. Operationally, we will lay heavy odds with anyone that the sun will come up. Likewise, we don't "trust" that Bank of America will give us our money back when we ask for it (modulor the right incantations and such): we _believe_ very strongly that it will. When people gain experience with a complex protocol, for example, and they start to see the same behavior, then they start to "trust" (= believe, = make bets) the protocol. Such was it when we were children making our first purchases with coins, such was it when we were teenagers, perhaps, and first began using checks ("You mean I can just write down a number, sign my name, and that's _money_?!"). Such was it with our first credit card usage, our first purchase of naked puts (don't ask), our first SSL-secured onlline purchase, our first use of Mark Twain Bank systems, and our first use of the First Bank of Cypherspace's newfangled blinding scheme. So, this is why asking whether people will "trust" abstract bits is the wrong question to ask, for at least two major reasons. --Tim May ""Guard with jealous attention the public liberty. Suspect everyone who approaches that jewel. Unfortunately, nothing will preserve it but downright force. Whenever you give up that force, you are ruined." --Patrick Henry